StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume - Essay Example

Cite this document
Summary
In his Treatise of Human Nature,Hume delineates his theory of human morality.The form of argument Hume takes is the concept that human morality is not based on coherent thought and logical reason, but is instead the upshot of humanity's passionate fervor…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER91.1% of users find it useful
A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume"

A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume A Treatise of Human Nature is not only David Hume's first philosophical work, it is also his most comprehensive execution of his massive contribution to the pursuit of human wisdom. Since its surprisingly tepid response from readers of the original edition, Hume's work has justifiably come to be regarded as one of the most significant works in the history of philosophy. In his Treatise of Human Nature, David Hume delineates his theory of human morality. The form of argument Hume takes is the concept that human morality is not based on coherent thought and logical reason, but is instead the upshot of humanity's passionate fervor. Since this fervor cannot present itself as the creation of logical reason, it would be consequently be the ultimate in the lack of logical thinking to adjudicate any moral deed as being the result of either rational or irrational thought. Hume delivers a succession of explanations that serve to reveal why humanity should express scepticism toward any conclusion based upon reasoning that is arrived at through familiarities based on sensory perception. Hume concludes that even in the face of complexities that are presented by virtue of the illogic inherent in sensory perception, humans still maintain a forcible belief in illogical conclusions due to psychology. This presents the paradoxical notion that strong belief is often grounded in contradictions. Hume's argument posits that it is even within the realm of possibility that the most grounded and confident reasonable conclusions are, in fact, merely probable and that the degrees of probability are subject to intense scrutiny with each additional analysis. Mistakes made on the basis of supposedly rational certainty are legion due to the inescapable imperfectability of human judgment. The ironic paradox of human judgment resides in the fact that each further analysis of the previous judgment decreases the probability of correctness in the original judgment. This has particularly chilling aspects when considered against the potential for reductions of probability in those elements that humans invest the utmost confidence in regarding the infallibility of correctness, such as laws of mathematics and science. Hume emphasises that there are three stipulations required to confirm merely through observation. The first he termed the aspect of constant conjunction, in which the cause and the effect are required to be both spatially and constantly extant. The second stipulates that the cause must have come before the effect itself. And finally, there must be a connection of necessity; that is it must be possible to ascertain why the cause produces the effect. Hume's appraisal of causation necessarily dictates that it can only be inferred and not examined and his conclusions indicate that it is impossible to achieve an impression of a necessary connection; rather, one must experience constant conjunction and temporal priority: "Experience only teaches us how one event constantly follows another, without instructing us in the secret connection which binds them together" (Hume, 1870, p. 347). Ultimately, Hume asserts that there are significant limitations to reason. Hume maintains that humans remain convinced that any object that is observed exists independently. Once this belief is subject to analysis, however, it is determined to be without basis and that paradox provides a basis for conflict in the process of reasonable determination. All perceptions are dependent upon human observation and even the slightest modification in the senses can distort that perception. Since this is one of the few absolute truths that exists, it is not logical to assume that perception can be something existing independently of us, nor can it possibly exist when there is nobody there to perceive it. Despite this Hume asserts that people will almost never surrender their natural belief in the existence of an external world that is separate from their perceptions. The argument of the bases for scepticism point toward the idea that Hume believes that scepticism itself is actually outside the realm of the possible due to the compulsion of natural belief: "Nature, by an absolute and uncontrollable necessity has determined us to judge as well as to breathe and feel." Nature compels humanity to acknowledge certain views even in the face of evidence to the contrary. The science of philosophy would potentially serve to make everyone utterly sceptical about the condition of the objects that are sensorily perceived if it were not for the fact that societal scepticism thwarts people from taking any philosophical argument too solemnly. Hume's dispute centers on the theory that it is impossible to think of a necessary connection through observation and that the concept one has of necessary connection occurs thusly. One experiences a steady concurrence of events A and B or repeated sense experiences where events resembling A are always followed by events resembling B. This manufactures a habit so that at any future appearance of A, one quite naturally expects B to follow. This, in turn, produces an internal feeling that passes from one thing another which in turn creates the sense from which the idea of necessary connection is drawn. A widespread but mistaken belief surrounding this topic is that necessity exists in the objects themselves. Hume explicate this erroneous belief by the natural tendency one possesses to accredit subjectively apparent qualities to objects. There are chains of cause that lead to every effect, whether or not they can be discovered they are presumed to exist. Along with contiguity is the concept of progression. The reason is obliged to precede the effect. An object can be contiguous and occur prior to another without being its cause, a necessary connection between the two need to be established. The relation of cause to effect does not depend on the known qualities of objects, but instead on the ideas of contiguity and succession, which are imperfect. Hume refutes the definition of cause as something productive of another, because reason and production are synonymous, and thus one definition using the other is circular. Hume questions why it is necessary that everything whose existence has a beginning, should also have a basis. He also questions why particular causes are required to have such particular effects, and why is an inference drawn from one to the other. The statement that whatever has a beginning has also a cause of existence is not implied by any of the relations of resemblance, proportions in quantity and number, degrees of any quality, or contrariety; therefore, it is not able to be refutable using reason. Using that logic states that everything that exists should have a beginning, thus needing a cause. If it didn't have a basis then it would have had to produce itself, and that logic would mean that it had to exist before it existed. That argument contradicts itself, because it uses itself as a basis for existence in its premise, when it is proving the concept of cause being a necessity. Consequently, it begs the question to prove cause and effect by relying on the conclusion to prove the premise. The ideas of cause and effect cannot vary too far from actual intuitions of the mind or ideas from the memory. One must first establish the existence of causes before one can infer effects from them. One have only two ways of doing that, either by an immediate perception of our memory or senses, called impressions, or, by an inference from other reasons, called thoughts. Regardless of the source of the feeling, the imagination and perceptions of the senses are the foundation for the reasoning that traces the relation of cause and effect. The inference that one draw from cause to effect does not come from a dependence on the two concepts to each other or from a rational objective look at the two. One object does not imply the existence of any other. All distinct ideas are separable, as are the ideas of cause and effect. The only way that one can infer the existence of one object from another is through understanding. Contiguity and succession are not sufficient to make us pronounce any two objects to be cause and effect, unless one perceive, that these two relations are preserved in several circumstances. Instances of which a person have had no familiarity, must resemble those, of which one has had experience. There is a transition from impression to plan, with the necessary connection possibly depending on the inference, instead of the inference depending on the necessary connection. The only connection or relation of objects, which can lead us beyond the immediate notions of our memory and senses, is that of cause and effect, because a person can base one inference from an object to another. The concept of cause and effect comes from past knowledge that informs us that some particular objects are conjoined with each other. There is, however, debate over whether a necessary connection exists between cause and effect. If cause and effect are connected, there should be a reason, or necessity for their connection. All of our thoughts are formed from impressions, consequently there must be an intuition that forms the conception of necessity, if there really is such an idea. The basis of necessity lies between cause and effect, therefore that is where the focus should turn. When two objects are presented before us, one cause the other effect, no tie will ever be perceived uniting the two. All ideas are founded in impressions. The necessary connection between causes and effects is the foundation of the inference from one to the other. Nevertheless, necessity only exists in the mind, not in physical material objects. The inspiration of the connection arises from the repetition of their union. That repetition doesn't change anything in the objects, or make them relate to each other, it only affects the mind. There are two definitive definitions of causality that Hume finally attains. He views them as either an object precedent and contiguous to another, where all the objects similar to the former are placed in a like relation of priority and contiguity to those objects that resemble the latter. The other definition can be viewed as an object precedent and contiguous to another, and thus combined with it in the imagination, so that the conception of the one determines the mind to form the thought of the other, and the feeling of the one to form a more lively inspiration of the other. Hume sees the second definition of cause as being more accurate. The precedent and contiguous object seems to cause the effect, but in reality cannot be used to reason a necessary connection between cause and effect. The ideas of cause and effect, though they may be real, can only be supported by experience. David Hume's argument in his epistemology on impressions and ideas mirrors his argument on causation. He looks at many of the same concepts, including contiguity, succession, and resemblance. Many of his arguments on causation refer back to the epistemology, concerning the connection between feelings and conceptions, as well as memory and the imagination. After comparing the two arguments there is only one rational end that you can come to, with the arguments being founded on the same premises and not contradicting each other, if you accept one, you must accept the other. Perceptions that enter the body with force form intuitions, including sensations, passions and emotions. Those impressions are formulated in the composition of ideas. Impressions and conceptions can be broken down into easy and complex. Straightforward perceptions or thoughts admit of no distinction or separation, where complex can be divided into parts. Ideas are solely formed from impressions, and cannot be separated from those impressions. Ideas and impressions always correspond to each other. You can, however, have complex thoughts of which you never had impressions that corresponded to them in the same order. Therefore, you can imagine all sorts of things that you have never seen, such as the golden mountain. Whenever a person thinks of something such as this they enjoin two separate and unswerving ideas that the have been presented with formerly and separately. Though there is a great resemblance between complex impressions and ideas, it can be safely assumed they are not exactly the same at all times. Effortless impressions, on the other hand, always form simple ideas that resemble them. The idea can differ in degree from the impression, but not in nature. If undemanding ideas and impressions resemble each other, and complex ideas are formed from simple ones, then easy and complex are exactly correspondent. Ideas are preceded by other more lively perceptions, from which they are derived, and which they represent. Simple impressions are prior to their correspondent ideas. There can be certain impressions, however, that can be preceded by ideas, as in the case of reflection. An impression can strike the senses, and a copy of it taken to the mind, which will remain even after the impression ceases. It forms a lasting idea. The memory and imagination copy that impression and make it into an idea that can eventually give rise to other impressions and ideas, making for an exception that still does follow the rules of impressions and ideas. There are forces that cause ideas to be associated with each other. They arise from resemblance, contiguity in time and place, and cause and effect. Hume's doctrine on causality follows many of the same ideas through the process of his epistemology, as does his definition of causality in his section on knowledge and probability. The first of the similarities lies with contiguity. Impressions and ideas are related, just as cause and effect are thought of as being related. There is also a perceived succession in both cases. Impressions precede ideas, just as a cause precedes effect. Even in the case of reflection, where a pre-conceived idea of the mind is there and can form other impressions, the initial impression comes before the idea. The concept of the impressions of the mind is one of the key pieces that associates Hume's epistemology and his argument on causation. Cause and effect are complex and distinct ideas of the mind that are spawned from impressions. Ideas are separable, therefore cause and effect are not necessarily associated. The ideas of cause and effect are contingent upon Hume's concept of impressions from his epistemology. Those impressions were formed from perceptions of relations between cause and effect, which are based on knowledge. Impressions, in essence, formed the idea of a necessary connection between cause and effect. Impressions are based on understanding, and the impression that formed the idea of a necessary relation between cause and effect was no different. The only reason for the idea of cause and effect being related was a previous experience, or custom that tied cause and effect together. Hume's doctrine on causality is firmly founded in the concepts from his epistemology. His theories on the relation between impressions and ideas tie in directly with his idea of a necessary connection between cause and effect. People have internal impressions that form the ideas of necessity, and those ideas are based on repetition and resemblance, but do not prove the claim that there is a necessary connection between cause and effect. Ideas are not original, they are formed from impressions and influenced by resemblance, and experience. Cause is not an original idea, it is formed from impressions, which are in turn formed from experience. Thus, we accept the idea of cause not because it is rational or well reasoned, but because of custom. Hume's position is consistent, and ultimately if you accept his epistemology, you must accept the reasoning behind his ideas on cause and effect. Hume's sceptical claim in regard to external objects is that we have no conception of the existence of external objects. Nevertheless, he argues, we do have an inescapable "vulgar" or common belief in the continued existence of objects, and this idea he accounts for. His explanation is lengthy, but involves the following features. Awareness of objects are disjointed and have no unity of themselves. In an effort to organize our acuity, we first naturally assume that there is no distinction between our insights and the objects that are perceived (this is the so-called "vulgar" view of perception). We then conflate all ideas of observation, which put our minds in similar dispositions. That is to say that people connect ideas that share a resemblance and attribute identity to their causes. Consequently, we naturally feign the continued and external existence of the objects or perceptions that produced these ideas. Lastly, we go on to believe in the existence of these objects because of the force of the resemblance between idea. Although this belief is philosophically unjustified, Hume feels he has given an accurate account of how we inevitably arrive at the idea of external existence. In contrast to the previous explanation of this idea, he recommends that we doubt a more sophisticated but erroneous notion of existence - the so-called philosophical view - which distinguishes between insights and external objects that cause perceptions. The psychological motivation for accepting this view is this: our imagination tells us that resembling perceptions have a continued existence, yet our reflection tells us that they are interrupted. Appealing to both forces, we ascribe interruption to acuities and continuance to objects. Hume's sceptical claim on the issue of personal identity is that we have no experience of a simple, individual impression that we can call the self, where the self is the entirety of a person's conscious life. Nevertheless, we do have an idea of personal identity that should be accounted for. He begins his explanation of this idea by noting that our perceptions are fleeting, and he concludes from this that all we are is a bundle of different perceptions. Because of the associative principles, though, the resemblance or causal connection within the chain of our discernments gives rise to an idea of oneself, and memory extends this idea past our immediate perceptions. A common abuse of the notion of personal identity occurs when the idea of a soul or unchanging substance is added to give us a stronger or more unified concept of the self. In all of these discussions, Hume performs an interesting balancing act between making sceptical attacks (step 1) and offering positive theories (step 2). In the conclusion to Book 1, though, he appears to elevate his scepticism to a higher level and exposes the inherent contradictions in even his best philosophical theories. He notes three such contradictions. One centers around what we call induction. Our judgments based on past experience all contain elements of doubt; we are then impelled to make a judgment about that doubt, and - since this too is based on past knowledge - this in turn will produce a new doubt. Once again, though, we are impelled to make a judgment about this second doubt, and the cycle continues. He concludes that "no finite object can subsist under a decrease repeated in infinitum." A second contradiction involves a conflict between two theories of external insight - our natural inclination to direct realism vs. the copy theory of perception of philosophers. The third contradiction involves a conflict between causal reasoning and belief in the continued existence of matter. It verges on the impossible to overlook the importance of David Hume and what his philosophical theories have contributed to the idea of necessity and perception. Hume conducted an autonomous understanding of causal inference and in doing so compelled all who came after him to inquire of themselves what is in one's mind before continuing on to infer the existence of one unambiguous thing from the existence of another. By doing this Hume has made it clear that humanity can no longer subsist by merely viewing things with the belief that there is a necessity that exists to their connection. David Hume has made it permanently evidence that people are not direct in their inferences by any extant insight but instead entirely by one's past experience. Although one is always insistent on incorporating situations to a similar one in nature, it always results in the discovery that only some objects emerge in habitual conjunction with others. It is due to these appearances and only these that one apprehends what specific causes or effects to anticipate in any fresh situation. That learning inhabit our consciousness in the form of customs. Once we have had experience, we approach all life with these particular habits of mind operative in us, so that we relate the coming events in the very definite ways that conform to our own experience. Thus causal inference is a very useful act of mind. The "necessity" we are aware of in causal reasoning is a feeling of such determination. Consequently, the atypical quality of which we are cognizant in the identity of an object or of one's own personal existence is a sentiment of the ready transition in our thought. Furthermore, whenever we are stirred by the very custom of our mind to conceive the existence of something remote from our presence we have a unique sentiment which we call belief. All these feelings mirror the quality of our mental progression in one's authentic perception of reality. Hume has provided for them in his dissection of the contents of the mind. In his taxonomy they are comprised of impressions of familiar knowledge and are inescapable components. In this way, for Hume, human knowledge is very much a matter of feeling as it is of ideas. It is analogous to a part of the mind similar to something like emotion and behavior. Works Cited Hume, D. (1921). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding: And Selections from a Treatise of Human Nature. Chicago: Open Court Publishing. Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(“A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume Essay”, n.d.)
A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume Essay. Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1518325-a-consideration-of-necessity-in-the-work-of-david-hume
(A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume Essay)
A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume Essay. https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1518325-a-consideration-of-necessity-in-the-work-of-david-hume.
“A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume Essay”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1518325-a-consideration-of-necessity-in-the-work-of-david-hume.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF A Consideration of Necessity in the Work of David Hume

A Consideration of Prison Ethics: Punishment vs. Rehabilitation

a consideration of Prison Ethics: Punishment vs.... One of the main issues in determining ethical ways of dealing with wrongdoers is that there needs to be an established set of roles and definitions that work within society to provide a system that all potential criminals are subject to....
5 Pages (1250 words) Essay

Philosophy of Morality by David Hume

This research will begin with the statement that an analysis of david hume's writings on religion must begin with a consideration of his moral theory.... According to david hume, reason alone is incapable of serving as the foundation of morality.... hellip; The conclusion states that it is difficult to imagine what hume could hope to gain by flattering the religious authorities at this late date.... The present research has identified that according to hume, we naturally approve of actions and qualities which we find either immediately agreeable or useful....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

David Hume and Immanuel Kant on our ideas of right and wrong

in the work An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Hume discusses the origin and association of ideas.... Philosophical ethics, as termed by david hume, deal with such questions and this branch of philosophy methodizes and, sometimes, corrects the practice in which human beings engage in everyday life.... david hume and Immanuel Kant are two of the most prominent philosophers to deal with the ides of right and wrong.... david hume (1711-1776), philosopher, historian, political theorist, social scientist, and essayist in his An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1758) and A Treatise of Human Nature (1739) provide a good knowledge about the understanding of right and wrong....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

Huge selling concentration

The essence of marketing lies in introducing the product into new geographical market.... The entering into new geographical market involves two aspects; 1.... Exporting, 2.... Manufacturing in new geographical market and selling those products there.... Hence, the considerations of any marketing manager differ in above two aspects and that results in analyzing or discussing two contexts in this paper while thinking about considerations of a marketing manager....
16 Pages (4000 words) Essay

Henry David Thoreau, Where I Lived and What I Lived For

?? However, he also begins to indicate how the appropriate living space isn't just the empty rooms and built spaces of human creation, but should include the shared spaces of the outdoors, the connection with nature and the consideration of the ultimate creation.... Henry david Thoreau insists, in his chapter entitled “Where I Lived and What I Lived For” in Walden, that the only way to live deliberately is to distance oneself completely from the rest of the world as a means of finding an internal alarm clock that would wake him up to… The essential concept behind this idea was that in living in places such as cities and towns, becoming regulated not by his own choices but by the necessity of earning food and board, most men tend to sleepwalk through life, only Where I Lived and What I Lived For Henry david Thoreau insists, in his chapter en d “Where I Lived and What I Lived For” in Walden, that the only way to live deliberately is to distance oneself completely from the rest of the world as a means of finding an internal alarm clock that would wake him up to really live life as it was meant to be experienced....
2 Pages (500 words) Essay

Cultural Considerations in the Design and Localisation of International Websites

These enterprises extend their business into the global market and most of them set up branches in many different countries as to provide their products or services directly in the… Such international enterprises are facing challenges from the global market.... Under the background of the modern information society, it is obvious that the Internet is already become one of the most effective ways to promote business....
14 Pages (3500 words) Essay

Potential for Acme Fireworks Company

These changes necessitate the owner and the management to review the existing structure of the Company because growth is anticipated to continue to the near future.... The… In addition, with the requirement of additional employees, equipment and more expected contracts, it is imperative that Acme re-position itself in order to protect the success The current business entity must be evaluated, and assessment made for any changes needed....
7 Pages (1750 words) Research Paper

Humes Posteriori Argument against Miracles is not Valid

"hume's Posteriori Argument against Miracles is not Valid" paper argues that although the first of hume's three 'a posteriori argument succeeds in showing that there may be no miracle proofs, it doesn't show that there is not a sufficient probability for establishing our test case.... hellip; In view of the fact that (contrary to hume's first 'a priori argument') the quantitative requirements for a miracle testimony need only be that of a successful probability as opposed to a proof; in view of the fact that our miracle test-case of the alleged resurrection of Jesus seems to satisfy the qualitative requirements of credible testimony....
7 Pages (1750 words) Coursework
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us