StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kants Deontological System - Essay Example

Cite this document
Summary
The paper "Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kants Deontological System" states that if Aristotle were alive today the last thing he would be is an Aristotelian if what it means to bean Aristotelian is to protect what will call a balanced hypothesis of internal relations…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER98.5% of users find it useful
Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kants Deontological System
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kants Deontological System"

Comparing and Contrasting Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kants Deontological System Virtue Ethics: Morality and Character Both the teleological - moral systems are illustrated mainly by a focus on the consequences which any action may have - and deontological - moral systems are characterized by a focus upon observance to independent moral rules or duties - ethical theories are described deontic or action-based hypothesis of ethics since they focus wholly upon the events which an individual carries out. Those hypotheses focus on the question that which action one ought to prefer. However, virtue ethics take a very dissimilar viewpoint. Fundamental virtue-based ethical hypotheses place not much of importance on which system people must pursue and in its place focus on serving people build up good natured individuality, for instance kindness and generosity. These temperament traits will permit an individual to make the proper decisions later on in life. Virtue theorists as well accentuate the need for people to study how to manage bad conduct of character, like insatiability or resentment. These are described as vices and stand in the way of creating a good individual. In recent time’s virtue ethics has not been a general topic for learning, however it goes back to the ancient Greek philosophers and is therefore the oldest kind of ethical theory in Western viewpoint. Plato talked on the subject of four vital virtues: wisdom, courage, temperance and justice. The earliest methodical explanation of virtue ethics was written down by Aristotle in his well-known work Nichomachean Ethics. According to Aristotle, when populace obtains good conduct of character, they are better capable to control their feelings and their cause. Further this assists to reach ethically right decisions while one is faced with complex alternatives. One of motive why virtue ethics can be admired and why they make a significant involvement to the perceptive of ethics is that they give emphasis to the essential function carried out by motives in ethical queries. To perform from virtue is to perform from some meticulous inspiration; consequently to say that certain virtues are essential for proper moral decisions is to say that proper moral decisions necessitate right motives. There is no need that teleological or deontological ethical theories necessitate reasons to play a role in the assessment of ethical decisions, although promoting proper inspirations is frequently an important constituent of the ethical education of youthful people. It is taught that one ought to wish certain results and that he must desire to achieve certain objectives by the performances. Yet another reason that virtue hypotheses are so attractive is that the other ethical theories contribute in common the complexity in dealing with intricate ethical computations over what actions to take or which ethical duties to stress. Virtue hypothesis assure that once someone is victorious in building the sort of individual he desire to be, reaching at the right ethical decisions will come obviously. Problems with Virtue Ethics The authenticity of virtue ethics isn’t as orderly and easy as someone might visualize. Even though several general ethical decisions may certainly come more effortlessly to an individual of the correct ethical personality, the fact is that a lot of ethical dilemmas need a great deal of cautious analysis and thinking. Simply encompassing the true character may not be sufficient to even formulate the right decision possibly. One more difficulty with virtue-based ethical systems is the inquiry of what the ‘correct’ type of quality is which an individual be supposed to have. Several virtue theorists have treated the answer to this inquiry as self-evident, however it is anything but. One individual’s virtue may be another person’s vice and a vice in particular set of situation may be a virtue in another. A few supporters of virtue principles propose that to decide the right virtues by asking a righteous person, however that is simply an exercise in question begging. Some may propose asking a happy person, but that takes for granted that happiness and virtue at all times concur. Possibly a key to understanding virtue hypotheses of ethics is to consider them as ways to move toward moral psychology however not ethical epistemology. This means that virtue theories must not be compared with hypotheses concerning how to create ethical options, like the teleological hypothesis of John Stuart Mill or the deontological hypothesis of Immanuel Kant. In its place, virtue hypotheses of morals should be considered as ways to know how one turn out to be ethical individuals, how one build up the means by which one take ethical decisions, and the progression by which moral outlooks grow. More significantly, virtue hypotheses may be capable to teach how ethics themselves ought to be educated; on the whole in the earliest years while the additional complex decision-making procedures are not yet feasible (Cline n. pg.). Utilitarianism Utilitarianism is predominantly wide-ranging and uncomplicated ethical theory. Its fundamental principle is that the correct action to carry out is the one which generates large amount cheerfulness. This welfare consequentially is in brief spoken by utilitarianisms most well-known initiator, Jeremy Bentham: "the greatest happiness of the greatest number is the foundation of morals and legislation” (Bentham 142).There are general differences over how this end ought to be understood and accomplished, but all utilitarian consider that it is the basis of moral values, not simply one thought amongst several. In the sense, it is a monistic more willingly than pluralistic ethical hypothesis. It consequently holds out the outlook of a great explanation and generalization of moral values, to decide complicated issues, all that require to do is think about how to maximize the equilibrium of happiness. Although it is as well runs the danger of missing something significant (Ash n. pg). The power of Utilitarianism has been extensive, pervading the academic life of the last two centuries. Its consequence in law, politics, and economics is particularly distinguished. The Utilitarian hypothesis of the rationalization of punishment stands against to the ‘retributive’ hypothesis, according to which punishment is planned to make the unlawful ‘compensate’ for his offense. As per the Utilitarian, the underlying principle of punishment is completely to stop further crime by either transformation the unlawful or defending humanity from him and to discourage others from crime through dread of punishment. In its political viewpoint Utilitarianism bases the power of government and the sacredness of individual privileges upon their usefulness, therefore providing an option to hypotheses of natural law, natural rights, or social agreement. What type of administration is most excellent therefore turns out to be a question of what kind of administration has the most consequences. An appraisal is needed that truthful grounds concerning human nature and behavior. Usually, Utilitarian have supported democratic system as a way of creating the attention of government concur with the broad interest; they have disputed for the maximum individual independence well-matched with an equal freedom for others on the ground that each person is normally the finest judge of his own welfare; and they have thought in the likelihood and the attractiveness of progressive social transform through peaceful political developments. With different truthful suppositions Utilitarian arguments can direct to diverse conclusions. Suppose the inquirer imagines that a strong administration is necessary to make sure mans fundamentally selfish interests and that any alteration may intimidate the permanence of the political order, he may be led by Utilitarian arguments to a dictatorial or conservative position. Alternatively, William Godwin, an early 19th-century political theorist, understood the fundamental integrity of human nature and argued that the most happiness would pursue from a essential change of the social order towards revolutionary Communism. Traditional finances established some of its vital testimonials from Utilitarian writers, especially Ricardo and John Stuart Mill. Paradoxically, its hypothesis of economic value was framed mainly in terms of the cost of labor in construction rather than in terms of the use value, or usefulness, of possessions. Later on improvements more obviously reflected the Utilitarian attitude. In financial strategy, the early Utilitarians had be inclined to oppose governmental intervention in trade and industry on the supposition that the economy would adjust itself for the maximum welfare if left alone; later Utilitarians, on the other hand, lost assurance in the social competence of private venture and were ready to see governmental authority and administration used to correct its misuse. As a movement for the reorganization of social institutions, 19th-century Utilitarianism was extraordinarily victorious in the long run. The majority of their suggestions have since been put into practice if not discarded by the reformers; and Utilitarian opinions are at the present usually engaged to advocate institutional or strategy transform. As a theoretical moral principle, Utilitarianism has recognized itself as one of the small numbers of live choices that have to be taken into account and either disproved or accepted by any theorist taking a position in normative principles. In modern-day debate it has been removed from accidental involvements with the analysis of moral language and with the psychosomatic hypothesis with which it was presented by Bentham. Utilitarianism currently appears in various customized and complex formulations. Benthams perfect of a hedonic calculus is typically well thought-out a practical if not a theoretical unfeasibility. Present-day theorists have became aware of further tribulations in the Utilitarian measures. One among them, for instance, is with the procedure of recognizing the consequences of an act. A procedure that is theoretical in addition to practical troubles as to what are to be taken into account as consequences, even with no accurately quantifying the worth of those consequences. There is as well complexity in the process of comparing substitute acts. If one act necessitates a prolonged period of time for its performance than another, one may inquire whether they can be considered options. Even what is to calculate as an act is not a subject of theoretical compromise. These tribulations are general to more or less all normative moral hypotheses because the majority of them identify the consequences of an act as being pertinent moral considerations. The fundamental insight of Utilitarianism, that one ought to encourage cheerfulness and stop discontent whenever feasible, seems irrefutable. However, the serious inquiry is that whether the entire of normative principles can be evaluated in terms of this simple method (West n. pg). Kants Deontological System This tension of ethical expression that argues that moral treatment is suitable to humans for the reason that of their judiciousness has a long history. Its most accepted recent embodiment is connected with the ethical thinking of the theorist Immanuel Kant. His outlook is of a type called ‘deontological’ for the reason that it aims to explain how there can be ethical necessities that do not depend on whether the actions required to create superior consequences. Kant took it be one’s particular capability as balanced beings to devise general or universal laws, which is what gave us ethical awareness. For any act that may consider doing, he can at all times inquire whether he would be willing to support a universal law that allowed or necessary that type of action. Fascinatingly, such questioning is noticeably like applying the Golden Rule to a probable action. If one contemplate cheating his neighbor, Kant would have him inquire whether he would be willing to live in a world in which people were all allowed to deceive one another which, certainly, would mean that he too would be subject to allowable cheating. Perhaps with an overindulgence of hopefulness, Kant accomplished that, not only would no one want to live in such a world, no one could truthfully will to live in one. Therefore, one must know that as a minimum in the heart of hearts that he is creating a particular exclusion for him that he would not grant others and that he cannot actually rationalize for him. Summing up, for Kant and those motivated by him, true ethics is a matter of treating human beings in ways that are suitable to their nature of free and rational beings.  And this explains that that care for them as free and rational, in ways that they can liberally and reasonably recognize.  When people protest, for instance, of being treated like substance or like utensils, they are fundamentally saying that they have been treated in ways that fall short to admire their liberty and judiciousness.  They have been maneuvered or oppressed more or less, rather than pleaded to for free and rational recognition.  Because freedom and rationality are taken to be the marks of personhood, a Kantian-type ethics is at times called a morality of admiration for persons.   Opposite to consequentialism, this kind of ethical advance evidently rules out using people as means to the contentment of others. For this cause, a lot of of those who have felt that utilitarianism is not a strong enough protector of individual human privileges, have turned to Kantian or Kantian-motivated ethical outlooks.  However, though there is certainly something about a Kantian-style ethic that resonates with many people’s strong feelings concerning the treatment appropriate to human beings, this type of move toward have its troubles as well.  Contrasting utilitarianism with its stress on contentment or the satisfaction of desires, Kantian ethical hypothesis doesn’t offer an easily-grasped concept of the good.  And many theorists have uncertainty whether in reality have a capability to make rational evaluations independent of desires (Leighton and Jeffrey n. pg). Since last two decades all have observed a renaissance of awareness in the virtues, an interest which, at a smallest amount, performs as a enhancement to the well-known options of deontology and utilitarianism, and, at a maximum, acts as a alternate for deontology and utilitarianism. James Wallace is educational here. While he started out with the extreme outlook that could organize with the idea of ethical rules or laws, he finally understood that this is a ineffective hope. Hartshorne, also, speaks passionately in favor of duties as restrictions which no righteous person can disobey. Further, it must be noted that a protector of the maximal outlook would as well appear to be dedicated to the stance that in the social order there should not be several inconsistent population, each nurturing dissimilar virtues, and this because in the maximal view there is no obvious rule for arbitrating disagreements among the values found in different groups of people. Further, Hartshorne assumes the minimal outlook in that his liberalism - whether standard or modern - entrust him to the probability that there will in fact be at variance the people fostering diverse virtues. Each section in the society is not only likely to have its own wellbeing but as well its own virtues. Therefore it is at least comprehensible why modern ethics is to some extent legalistic. By way of contrast, Aristotle dealt with a small face-to-face group of people where the possible phronimoi were famous in that they frequently came from the well-respected families. For the reason that virtue theorists inclined to trace their lineage back to Aristotle, while they talk about the connection between ethics and metaphysics they as well tend to do so in Aristotelian terms, particularly in terms of a natural teleology that tries to decide which well-designed possessions are necessary for a full human life. Aristotle have the same opinion that some natural progressions have final in addition to material and competent causes, but the actions in a person’s life are not goal-oriented simply because they accomplish some outcome that might have been their objective. Future consequences can be pertinent in clearing up why certain preceding actions may have occurred without really having been the causes of those actions. This point is critical in the attempt to demonstrate the continuity between Aristotle and Hartshorne concerning the metaphysical basis for virtue ethics. If Aristotle were alive today the last thing he would be is an Aristotelian if what it means to bean Aristotelian is to protect what will call a balanced hypothesis of internal relations. Those who do build up a commencement of the final good, of the good to be accomplished in the entire life, habitually shun errors in practical reasoning and option, but not even they are protected from adversity striking or from unexpected future contingencies forcing them to completely change their plans. Apparent, unambiguous plans for the future are only marginally more victorious than the rough, implicit ones developed by the majority people. An additional precise vision would be that all human beings characteristically direct their actions by practical reason; the point is not that all ought to aim at a maximum achievable distance from other creatures on the subject of capability to envisage how future contingencies will ultimately be actualized (Dombrowski 152-165). Work Cited Ash, T. Utilitarianism Big Issue Ground, 2003, 30 April 2009 Benthams Works, Vol. x. p. 142. (2003) Cline, A., Virtue Ethics: Morality and Character 30 April 2009 Dombrowski, D. Hartshorne, Metaphysics and The Law of Moderation Process Studies, pp. 152-165, Vol. 21, Number 3 1992. 30 April 2009 Leighton, P. and Jeffrey. Deontological & Kantian Ethics CJ Ethics 2001. 30 April 2009 West, H.R. Utilitarianism From Encyclopædia Britannica. 30 April 2009 Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(“Comparing and Contrasting Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kant's Essay”, n.d.)
Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1554594-comparing-and-contrasting-virtue-ethics-utilitarianism-and-kants-deontological-system
(Comparing and Contrasting Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kant'S Essay)
https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1554594-comparing-and-contrasting-virtue-ethics-utilitarianism-and-kants-deontological-system.
“Comparing and Contrasting Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kant'S Essay”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1554594-comparing-and-contrasting-virtue-ethics-utilitarianism-and-kants-deontological-system.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF Virtue Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Kants Deontological System

Physician-Assisted Suicide

Physician-assisted suicide enjoys little legal acceptance, a situation that has also infected larger religious and ethics bodies in many countries who continue to sternly oppose the practice.... Society is regarded to be one big area that accommodates people with different social, cultural, psychological, political and economic values who also intermingle frequently....
9 Pages (2250 words) Research Paper

Ethics of Living and Dying

In their work, as well as in the personal lives, these individuals are morally bound, according to deontological theories, to the commitments naturally arising from the categorical imperative.... The essay "ethics of Living and Dying" talks about the iatrogenesis which is often caused by medical error or negligence, instrument design, social control (in cases of psychotherapy), medical anxiety, and negative interactions between medications.... In the case of iatrogenesis, it is often assumed that like other issues in medical ethics, iatrogenesis is grounded in the duty (or implicit contract) that healthcare givers allegedly have toward the patients receiving their care....
8 Pages (2000 words) Essay

Ethical Theories: Description And Application

Unlike utilitarianism and Deontological theories, which are systems that give you a system on which to base your actions, Hume's theory is empirical, meaning he describes his observations on how people tend to think and feel about morality.... These theories include Deontology and Utilitarianism, as well as the moral theory of David Hume, which is a type of virtue ethics.... Consequentialism is a system of ethics where the moral statuses of actions are based on their consequences, rather than on the actions themselves....
5 Pages (1250 words) Research Paper

Ethics and Public Administration

As early mentioned, public services is guided by ethical theories based on the nature of their public work, for instance, some political service and behavior support deontological ethics theory.... deontological theory is a duty or obligation grounded ethics, and deontologists assert that ethical rules bind government people s to their duty and they consider the right or wrong aspect of the action and not the effects of the action consequences, (Coady, 2006, p....
10 Pages (2500 words) Essay

Analysis of Ethical Systems

The third theory differs from the first two since it emphasizes the character of a person and is referred to as virtue ethics (Schlabach: 186).... hesis Statement: The purpose of this paper is to analyze the ethical system of Deontology.... This ethical system will be applied to a Case Study.... deontological theories can be defined by their opposition to consequentialism in the fundamental determination of concepts related to morally right or According to deontological theory, “moral values and standards cannot be determined at any level of analysis by what would promote the best outcomes or states, assessed agent-neutrally” (Darwall: 1)....
12 Pages (3000 words) Admission/Application Essay

Different Ways of Solving Ethical Problems

The teleological and deontological evaluations lead to ethical judgments and which finally result in the intentions (Antoine & Green, n.... utilitarianism believes in doing well to the maximum number of people (Smith, 2010).... The paper "Different Ways of Solving Ethical Problems" states that various theories on ethical marketing further reinforce the fact that companies should abide by ethics in their marketing activities....
9 Pages (2250 words) Case Study

A Vision of the Good Life

In reflection of varied moral theories, such as utilitarianism and deontological perceptions, every individual has the course to actively seeking their happiness.... Thus, according to the deontological theory, an action must accomplish the duty for the sake of duty.... On the contrary, deontological philosophy advocates for the best outcome, in which all entities receive the correct oral action depending on the rules, laws, and intuition (Goodin, 1995)....
9 Pages (2250 words) Assignment

The Fable of Education as Commodity

This report "The Fable of Education as Commodity" presents the fable of education as a commodity that is about Deidre's experiences while directing a city-wide volunteer agency.... Deidre noticed the increasing number of people seeking voluntary work and most of them were from the middle class.... ...
12 Pages (3000 words) Report
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us