StudentShare
Contact Us
Sign In / Sign Up for FREE
Search
Go to advanced search...
Free

The Structure of Scientific Revolutions - Book Report/Review Example

Cite this document
Summary
This book review "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" focuses on Thomas Kuhn who has reacted against other philosophies in his research. He states that other creative fields exhibit some sort of progress. A great example is a theologian who expresses dogma…
Download full paper File format: .doc, available for editing
GRAB THE BEST PAPER94.6% of users find it useful
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions
Read Text Preview

Extract of sample "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

College: Thomas Kuhn has reacted against other philosophy in his research. He s that other creative fields exhibit some sort of progress. An example is the theologian who expresses dogma or the philosopher who makes the Kantian imperatives refined contributes to development, if only to that of the group that has a share in his premises. He further illustrates that no creative school recognizes a grouping of work that is a creative success, but is not an addition to the group’s communal achievement. According to him, if we doubt, as many do, that non-scientific fields do progress, that is not because individual schools do not (Kuhn 1962). It is because there are always competing schools that normally questions the very foundations of the rest. An individual with an argument that philosophy has made no progress has emphasis on the fact that there are still Aristotelians and not that Aristotelianism has failed to advance. Kuhn further illustrates that in music, the graphic arts, and literature, the practitioner gets his education by contact with the works of other artists, mainly earlier artists (Kuhn 1962). He explains that textbooks, except compendia or handbooks of original creations give only a secondary role. In philosophy, history, and the social sciences, textbook literature has a superior implication. In these fields, the basic college course uses parallel readings in original sources, some being the “classics” of the field, others the contemporary research reports written by practitioners for each other. This results in the student in any one of these disciplines to be constantly made aware of the immense range of problems that will be experienced by the members of his future group with time. More important, he has continually before him a range of competing and incommensurable keys to these problems, solutions that he has to ultimately assess for himself. Are crises an essential prerequisite for the emergence of new theories? How do scientists respond to their existence? According to Kuhn, part of the answer can be discovered by taking note first what scientists never do when faced with even severe and prolonged abnormalities (Kuhn 1962). Although they may begin to give up and then to consider options, they do not renounce the paradigm that led them into crisis. They do not treat anomalies as counter-instances, even though in the language of science philosophy, that is what they are. Partly, this generalization is a simple statement from historic fact that is based upon examples like those above. He further states that once it has attained the paradigm status, a scientific theory is acknowledged as invalid only if an alternating candidate is available to replace it. There is no process that has been disclosed by the historical study of scientific progress at all that looks like the methodological typecast of distortion by direct comparison with nature (Kuhn 1962). This remark does not show that scientists do not discard scientific theories, or that experience as well as experiment is not indispensable to the course in which they do so. But it means what will eventually be a vital point that the judgment act that leads scientists to refuse a formerly acknowledged theory is normally based on more than a judgment of that theory with the world. The decision to discard one paradigm is normally simultaneously the decision to admit another, and the ruling leading to that decision involves the evaluation of both paradigms with each other and nature (Kuhn 1962). Another reason for doubting that scientists reject paradigms due to confrontation with counter instances or anomalies according to Kuhn is that counter instances prevalent epistemological theory (Kuhn 1962). He argues they can at best help to create a crisis or more precisely, to strengthen one that is already in existence. By themselves they are unable to make the philosophical theory false because its defenders will do what other scientists do when confronted by anomaly. They normally devise many expressions and ad hoc amendments of their theory in order to get rid of any clear conflict. Most of the pertinent adjustments and qualifications are already in the literature. If indeed these epistemological counter instances are to be part of more than a minor irritant that will be due to the fact that they help to allow the emergence of a novel and different science analysis within which they will no longer cause trouble. In addition to this, if a typical pattern is applicable here, these irregularities will then no longer appear to be simply facts. From inside, a new theory of scientific knowledge may in its place appear very much like tautologies, reports of situations that could not possibly have been otherwise (Kuhn 1962). How then do scientists respond to the consciousness of an irregularity in the fit between nature and theory? What have just been stated shows that even an inconsistency unaccountably superior to that experienced in other applications of the theory should not draw any very thoughtful response. It is impossible to do way with all discrepancies. Even the most obstinate ones more often than not respond at last to normal practice. Often scientists are keen to wait, mainly if there are many problems existing in other parts of the field. We can note that, for example, that in the sixty years after Newton’s original computation, the forecasted motion of the moon’s perigee remained only half of what was seen. Even as the best mathematical physicists in Europe continued to wrestle unsuccessfully with the well-known inconsistency, there were sporadic proposals for a revision of Newton’s inverse square law. No one took these proposals seriously, and this patience in practice with a major anomaly proved justified. Clairaut in 1750 managed to show that only the mathematics of the application had been incorrect and that Newtonian theory could remain as before. Even in cases that no mere mistake appears quite possible. This could be because the mathematics concerned is simpler or of a familiar and elsewhere successful type. In this case constant and recognized irregularity does not always encourage crisis. No one critically questioned Newtonian theory since the long-recognized inconsistency between predictions from that hypothesis and both the velocity of sound as well as the motion of Mercury. The very first discrepancy was eventually and quite suddenly resolved by tests on heat embarked on for a very dissimilar purpose; the second one vanished with the common hypothesis of relativity after a crisis that it had had no role in forming. It then follows that if an irregularity is to induce crisis, it must habitually be more than just an anomaly. There always exist difficulties in the model nature fit; most of them are put right in the end, often by processes that may have not been foreseen. The scientist that pauses to look at every anomaly he notes will rarely get important work done. This therefore leads us to ask what it is that makes an anomaly appear worth intensive scrutiny, and to this question there probably is no fully general answer. The cases already examined are characteristic but hardly prescriptive. Sometimes an anomaly clearly calls into question clear in addition to basic generalizations of the paradigm. As we have already seen, on the other hand, that one of the things a scientific community obtains with a paradigm is a decisive factor for choosing issues that, while the model is taken for granted, can be understood to have solutions. To a large extent these are the only issues that the society will confess as scientific or persuade its members to take on. Other problems which include many that had beforehand been standard are discarded as metaphysical, as the apprehension of another discipline, or at times as just too difficult to merit the time. A model can, for that matter, even shield the society from those socially significant problems that cannot be reduced to the puzzle form, because they are able to be stated in terms of the theoretical and instrumental tools the model supplies. This type of problems can be an interruption, a lesson radiantly illustrated by more than a few facets of seventeenth-century Baconianism as well as by some of the modern social sciences. One of the reasons that makes normal science seems to advance so rapidly is that its practitioners focus on troubles that only their own lack of originality should prevent them from solving. If, on the other hand, the troubles of normal science are mysteries in this sense, we no longer need to ask why scientists show aggression to them with such fervor and devotion. A man could be attracted to science for all manner of reasons. Among them is the excitement of discovering new territory, the desire to be useful, the hope of getting order, and the drive to put established knowledge to test. These motives along with others also help to establish the exacting problems that will at a later time engage him. In addition, though the result is irregular frustration, there is an excellent reason why such motives should at first is a focus for him and then lead him from then. The scientific venture as a whole always proves useful from time to time, display order, opens up new territory, and experiment long-accepted belief. Nonetheless, the person occupied with a normal research issue is nearly never doing any one of these things. Once occupied, his drive rather changes to some other sort. What then poses a challenge to him is the confidence that, if only he is more skilful, he will have success in solving a mystery that no one else has ever solved before. When we examine the record of past researches from the vantage of contemporary historiography, the science historian may be tempted to conclude that a change in paradigms changes to the world too. Led by a fresh paradigm, scientists take on new instruments and look in places that are new. Even more significant, during revolutions scientists perceive new and dissimilar things when observing with familiar instruments in places they have tested before. It is somewhat as if the professional community has been abruptly taken to another planet where common objects are observed in a different light and are united by unfamiliar ones as well. Of course, nothing like that sort really occurs: there is no physical transplantation; outside the laboratory daily affairs generally continue as before. Nonetheless, paradigm changes do cause scientists to perceive the globe of their research-engagement in a different way. In thus far as their only alternative to that world is in the course of what they see as well as do, we may conclude that after a revolution scientists respond to a different world. Some of these are the results of the unparalleled insulation of scientific communities that are mature from the requirements of the laity and of daily life. That filling has never been whole, now we are discussing issues of degree. On the other hand, there exists no other professional community in which personal creative work is so solely addressed to and assessed by other members of the same profession. The most obscure of poets or the most conceptual of theologians is a lot more concerned than the scientist with limited consent of his creative work, even though he may be even of less concern with approval in general. That disparity proves of consequence. Just because he works only for viewers of colleagues, an audience that shares his own beliefs and values, the scientist could have a single set of standards for granted. He needs not to worry about what some other school or group will think and can therefore set out of one problem and move on to the next more quickly than those working for a more sacrilegious group. Even more vital, the insulation of the scientific community from society allows the individual scientist to focus his attention upon issues that he has good reason to deem he is likely to solve. Distinctly from the engineer, and most doctors, and many theologians, the scientist does not need to choose problems because they immediately need solution and without considering the tools available for the solution to be attained. In this esteem, also, the difference between many social scientists and natural scientists proves useful. The former often tend, as the later almost never do, to have their choice of a research problem defended. An example is the racial discrimination effects or the reason of the business cycle primarily in terms of the social significance of getting a solution. Which of this group would we then expect to solve issues at a quicker rate? The consequences of insulation from the bigger society are very much pronounced by another feature of the proficient scientific community, the character of its educational beginning. In comparing this state with that in at least the current natural sciences, in these fields the student depends largely on textbooks till in his third or fourth year of graduate work when he begins his own research. Most science curricula will not ask even graduate students to read in areas not written specifically for students. The minority that does assign additional reading in monographs and research papers restricts such assignments to the most superior courses and to resources that take up more where the accessible texts leave off. Until the very final stages in the scientist’s education, textbooks are methodically replaced for the creative scientific literature that made them probable. Given the self-assurance in their paradigms, this makes this educational practice possible, not many scientists would wish to modify it. Is there a reason for a student of physics to read works by Faraday, Einstein, Newton or Schrödinger, when all he needs to know on these works is summed up in a far briefer, more accurate, and more methodical form in several up-to-date textbooks? Without the wish to defend the extreme lengths to which this kind of education has infrequently been done, one is forced to help but notice that generally it has been vastly effectual. Work cited Thomas Kuhn. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962. Read More
Cite this document
  • APA
  • MLA
  • CHICAGO
(“History and Philosophy Science Book Report/Review”, n.d.)
Retrieved from https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1609407-history-and-philosophy-science
(History and Philosophy Science Book Report/Review)
https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1609407-history-and-philosophy-science.
“History and Philosophy Science Book Report/Review”, n.d. https://studentshare.org/miscellaneous/1609407-history-and-philosophy-science.
  • Cited: 0 times

CHECK THESE SAMPLES OF The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

Thomas Kuhns Impact on Science Education: What Lessons Can be Learned by Matthews, M. R

According to Matthews (2003), when Kuhn wrote The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, created an entirely different conceptualization of science and in doing so impacted 'science education theory and research' (p.... Nevertheless, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions influenced philosophical argument disproportionate to the philosophical discussion contained in the actual book.... Regardless, Kuhn still managed to articulate an apparently 'new' and 'epistemological paradigm, or theory of scientific knowledge' (Matthews, 2003, p....
21 Pages (5250 words) Assignment

Implications of Artificial Separation Between Science and Society

This essay "Implications of Artificial Separation Between Science and Society" examines the ways through which the artificial separation between science and society fetters the future and the free development of scientific and engineering practices.... The supposed neutral space of scientific production can be unscientific in multiple ways as the so-called scientific space is actively related to the social space and the multiple constraining factors active therein....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE: DISCIPLINE AND SCIENCE

One important aspect that distinguishes Kuhn's model of scientific knowledge and the exceptionalist model is that Kuhn does not see a linear, steady, or uniform rate of evolution in scientific progress but one that changes in paradigm shifting moments related to technological innovation, new invention, and groundbreaking discoveries that radically alter the way science perceives or conceives the universe.... In this version of evolutionary ‘scientific exceptionalism', knowledge production is cumulative, convergent and progressive....
4 Pages (1000 words) Essay

Postmodern Philosophy on Thomas Kuhn

The Paradigm Shift Concept in Kuhn's terms Paradigm, in the terms of Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions", refers to the frame of thought that the scientists of today choose to adopt and the slowly evolving process that comprises inventions and discoveries as the need for these developments arises.... This essay "Postmodern Philosophy on Thomas Kuhn" focuses on Thomas Samuel Kuhn who shook the world of science with 'the structure of Science Revolutions'....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

Full Description of Hesss Concepts

Kuhn's book, 'The Structure of Scientific Revolutions,' evaluates the history of Science.... Kuhn's ideas related to the scientific revolution.... uhn illustrates that science has not developed from the accretion of factual information but continuously transforming situations and probabilities for the people related to scientific disciplines (Polsby, 1998).... he movie is based on Kuhn's ideas linked to the discovery of new concepts in the scientific field....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

The Structure of Scientific Revolution and Varieties of Religious Experience

The paper "the structure of scientific Revolution and Varieties of Religious Experience" states that concept is applicable to the understanding of religion, as proclaimed by James because religion is anything but restricted to logic and facts.... In his book the structure of scientific Revolution, Kuhn broadly defines all scientific discoveries as those that have adhered with time to current facts and information and those that require further experimentation and study....
6 Pages (1500 words) Essay

The Importance of Kuhns Scientific Revolution Theory

The paper "The Importance of Kuhns scientific Revolution Theory" states that the studies conducted by Dr Jill and Paco have successfully proved the importance of Kuhns scientific Revolution theory since it has once again questioned the findings that were made by previous researches....
7 Pages (1750 words) Term Paper

Philosophy and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions

The author of this paper "Philosophy and The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" examines the scientific revolution process, the sole scientific method, and scientific theories, the main modern philosopher's thoughts on scientific approaches, issues in the field of science that require values.... Constant literature about the history of science makes the revolutions seem real....
10 Pages (2500 words) Essay
sponsored ads
We use cookies to create the best experience for you. Keep on browsing if you are OK with that, or find out how to manage cookies.
Contact Us